Professor of Economics · Durham University Business School
View CVI am a Professor of Economics at the Durham University Business School and Director of the Durham Research in Economic Analysis and Mechanisms (DREAM Research Centre). My research interests include decision theory, game theory, experiments and finance.
My main research focuses on the role that uncertainty, information and bounded perception have on single- and multi-agent decision making. I study when information is valuable and whether markets (including the prediction markets) aggregate and reveal information through their price mechanism, when traders are ambiguity averse or they can acquire costly signals. I examine under which conditions speculative trade occurs in several settings: when there is a possibility of insider trading, when traders have a bounded perception of their uncertainty due to their unawareness, when they are dynamically and time inconsistent, and when they are not financially sophisticated enough to formulate complex trading strategies.
Previously, I was Associate Professor (Reader) and Head of the Department of Economics of City, University of London. Between 2007-2018, I was first a Lecturer and then an Associate Professor at the Department of Economics of the University of Southampton. I received my PhD from the University of Rochester, my MSc from the University of Warwick and my BSc from the Athens University of Economics and Business, all in Economics.
Games and Economic Behavior, 2025
No trade theorems examine conditions under which agents cannot agree to disagree on the value of a security which pays according to some state of nature, thus preventing any mutual agreement to trade. A large literature has examined conditions which imply no trade, such as relaxing the common prior and common knowledge assumptions, as well as allowing for agents who are boundedly rational or ambiguity averse. We contribute to this literature by examining conditions on the private information of agents that reveals, or verifies, the true value of the security. We argue that these conditions can offer insights in three different settings: insider trading, the connection of low liquidity in markets with no trade, and trading using public blockchains and oracles. Preprint
Review of Economic Studies, 2024
We study information aggregation in a dynamic trading model with partially informed and ambiguity averse traders. We show theoretically that separable securities, introduced by Ostrovsky (2012) in the context of Subjective Expected Utility, no longer aggregate information if some traders have imprecise beliefs and are ambiguity averse. Moreover, these securities are prone to manipulation, as the degree of information aggregation can be influenced by the initial price, set by the uninformed market maker. These observations are also confirmed in our experiment, using prediction markets. We define a new class of strongly separable securities which are robust to the above considerations, and show that they characterize information aggregation in both strategic and non-strategic environments. We derive several theoretical predictions, which we are able to confirm in the lab. Preprint
National Institute Economic Review, 2021
An often overlooked strategy for fighting the COVID-19 pandemic is group testing. Its main advantage is that it can scale, enabling the regular testing of the whole population. We argue that another advantage is that it can induce social distancing. Using a simple model, we show that if a group tests positive and its members are in close social proximity, then they will rationally choose not to meet. The driving force is the uncertainty about who has the virus and the fact that the group cares about its collective welfare. We therefore propose identifying socially connected groups, such as colleagues, friends and neighbours, and testing them regularly. Preprint
Economic Theory, 2021
Ambiguity sensitive preferences must fail either Consequentialism or Dynamic Consistency (DC), two properties that are compatible with subjective expected utility and Bayesian updating, while forming the basis of backward induction and dynamic programming. We examine the connection between these properties in a general environment of convex preferences over monetary acts and find that, far from being incompatible, they are connected in an economically meaningful way. In single-agent decision problems, positive value of information characterises one direction of DC. We propose a weakening of DC and show that one direction is equivalent to weakly valuable information, whereas the other characterises the Bayesian updating of the subjective beliefs which are revealed by trading behavior. Preprint
B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics, 2021
The ability of markets to aggregate information through prices is examined in a dynamic environment with unawareness. We find that if all traders are able to minimally update their awareness when they observe a price that is counterfactual to their private information, they will eventually reach an agreement, thus generalising the result of Geanakoplos and Polemarchakis [1982]. Moreover, if the traded security is separable, then agreement is on the correct price and there is information aggregation, thus generalizing the result of Ostrovsky [2012] for non-strategic traders. We find that a trader increases her awareness if and only if she is able to become aware of something that other traders are already aware of and, under a mild condition, never becomes aware of anything more. In other words, agreement is more the result of understanding each other, rather than being unboundedly sophisticated. Preprint
Journal of Public Economic Theory, 2021
In environments with expected utility, it has long been established that speculative trade cannot occur (Milgrom and Stokey [1982]), and that the value of public information is negative in economies with risk-sharing and no aggregate uncertainty (Hirshleifer [1971], Schlee [2001]). We show that these results are still true even if we relax expected utility, so that either Dynamic Consistency (DC) or Consequentialism is violated. We characterise no speculative trade in terms of a weakening of DC and find that Consequentialism is not required. Moreover, we show that a weakening of both DC and Consequentialism is sufficient for the value of public information to be negative. We therefore generalise these important results for convex preferences which contain several classes of ambiguity averse preferences. Preprint
Games and Economic Behavior, 2018
What are the implications on trading activity if investors are not sophisticated enough to understand and evaluate trades that have a complex payoff structure? Can frictions generated by this type of financial complexity be so severe that they lead to a complete market freeze, like that of the recent financial crisis? Starting from an allocation that is not Pareto optimal, we find that whether complexity impedes trade depends on how investors perceive risk and uncertainty. For smooth convex preferences, such as subjective expected utility, complexity cannot halt trade, even in the extreme case where each investor is so unsophisticated that he can only trade up to one Arrow-Debreu security, without being able to combine two or more in order to construct a complex trade. However, for non-smooth preferences, which allow for kinked indifference curves, such as maxmin expected utility, complexity can completely shut down trade. Preprint
Games and Economic Behavior, 2018
“No trade” theorems establish that, in various trading environments, investors who share a common prior will not engage in speculation, as long as expected utility, Bayesian updating and full awareness are imposed. We relax the last assumption by allowing for asymmetric unawareness and examine under which conditions speculative behavior emerges. We find that if common knowledge is assumed (as in the settings of Aumann [1976] and Milgrom and Stokey [1982]), unawareness cannot generate speculation. This is not true, however, in settings where no common knowledge is assumed, such as speculation in equilibrium (Geanakoplos [1989]) and betting that is always beneficial (Morris [1994]), unless stronger conditions on awareness are imposed. Preprint
Games and Economic Behavior, 2016
The value of information is examined in a risk-sharing environment with unawareness and complete markets. Information and awareness are symmetric among agents, who have a clear understanding of their actions and deterministic payoffs. We show with examples that public information can make some agents strictly better off at the expense of others, contrasting the standard results of Hirshleifer [1971] and Schlee [2001] that the value of public information is negative for all when risk averse agents are fully insured. We identify the source of this problem to be that, as awareness varies across states, it creates an awareness signal that the agents misunderstand and treat asymmetrically. As a result, risk-sharing opportunities that are available when this signal is not used, vanish when it is used. We identify a property, Conditional Independence, which we show is sufficient for the value of public information to be negative for all. Preprint
Journal of Economic Theory, 2015
The value of information is examined in a single-agent environment with unawareness. Although the agent has a correct prior about events he is aware of and has a clear understanding of his available actions and payoffs, his unawareness may lead him to commit information processing errors and to behave suboptimally. As a result, the value of information can be negative, contrasting what is true in the standard model with partitional information and no unawareness. We show that the source of the agent’s suboptimal behavior is that he misunderstands the information revealed by his varying awareness, treating it asymmetrically. Preprint
Games and Economic Behavior, 2013
We develop an approach to providing epistemic conditions for admissible behavior in games. Instead of using lexicographic beliefs to capture infinitely less likely conjectures, we postulate that players use tie-breaking sets to help decide among strategies that are outcome-equivalent given their conjectures. A player is event-rational if she best responds to a conjecture and uses a list of subsets of the other players’ strategies to break ties among outcome-equivalent strategies. Using type spaces to capture interactive beliefs, we show that event-rationality and common belief of event-rationality (RCBER) imply S∞W, the set of admissible strategies that survive iterated elimination of dominated strategies. By strengthening standard belief to validated belief, we show that event-rationality and common validated belief of event-rationality (RCvBER) imply IA, the iterated admissible strategies. We show that in complete, continuous and compact type structures, RCBER and RCvBER are nonempty, hence providing epistemic criteria for S∞W and IA. Preprint
Economic Theory, 2013
This paper provides a set-theoretic model of knowledge and unawareness. A new property called Awareness Leads to Knowledge shows that unawareness of theorems not only constrains an agent’s knowledge, but also can impair his reasoning about what other agents know. For example, in contrast to Li (J Econ Theory 144:977– 993, 2009), Heifetz et al. (J Econ Theory 130:78–94, 2006) and the standard model of knowledge, it is possible that two agents disagree on whether another agent knows a particular event. The model follows Aumann (Ann Stat 4:1236–1239, 1976) in defining common knowledge and characterizing it in terms of a self-evident event, but departs in showing that no-trade theorems do not hold. Preprint
Theory and Decision, 2011
We provide a syntactic model of unawareness. By introducing multiple knowledge modalities, one for each sub-language, we specifically model agents whose only mistake in reasoning (other than their unawareness) is to underestimate the knowledge of more aware agents. We show that the model is a complete and sound axiomatization of the set-theoretic model of Galanis (University of Southampton Discussion paper 709, 2007) and compare it with other unawareness models in the literature. Preprint
Working Paper, April 2025. Extended abstract in ACM EC 2024.
We study information aggregation in a dynamic trading model with partially informed traders. Ostrovsky [2012] showed that ‘separable’ securities aggregate information in all equilibria, however, separability is not robust to small changes in the traders’ private information. To remedy this problem, we allow traders to acquire signals with cost κ, in every period. We show that ‘κ separable securities’ characterize information aggregation and, as the cost decreases, almost all securities become κ separable, irrespective of the traders’ initial private information. Moreover, the switch to κ separability happens not gradually but discontinuously, hence even a small decrease in costs can result in a security aggregating information. We provide a complete classification of securities in terms of how well they aggregate information, which surprisingly depends only on their payoff structure.
Working Paper, March 2018
We provide a theory of the Laffer curve (LC) using a simple model of tax evasion with strategic complementarities, which arise from the assumption that the cost of being caught while evading is decreasing as more people evade their taxes. We find that with either sufficiently low or sufficiently high tax rates, there is a unique equilibrium, therefore a unique level of tax evasion and tax revenues. If taxes are in between, there can be multiple equilibria which imply two LCs, one with high and one with low tax evasion. The policy implication of this result is that if taxes are sufficiently high, it is possible to increase tax revenues by reducing taxes, even though locally the LC was upward sloping. Using data on VAT evasion, we find empirical evidence that supports our assumption of strategic complementarities and the presence of multiple LCs. Finally, we provide a numerical example by calibrating the LCs for Greece and show that an increase in the VAT rate would reduce tax revenues.
Working Paper, March 2016
The speculative trade theorem specifies that a positive common prior, which assigns positive probability to all elements of the join of the agents’ partitions, implies that there can be no mutually beneficial trade that is common knowledge at some state. We show that the reverse is also true for full support type structures, where at each state a type assigns positive probability to the element of the join that contains this state. By providing this behavioral characterization of positive common priors, we complement the existing result of the literature, that for arbitrary type structures there is a (not necessarily positive) common prior if and only if there is no mutually beneficial trade that is common knowledge at all states.
IZA Discussion Paper No.8442, August 2014
We report results from a sender-receiver deception game, which tests whether an individual’s decision to deceive is influenced by a concern for relative standing in a reference group. The sender ranks six possible outcomes, each specifying a payoff for him and the receiver. A message is then transmitted to the receiver, announcing that the sender has ranked the outcomes according to the receiver’s payoff, from highest to lowest. The receiver, without knowing that there is conflict of interest, chooses an action that determines the payoff of both players. The sender has an incentive to deceive the receiver, in order to obtain a higher payoff. A sender is positively biased if he thinks that he is higher in the deception distribution than in reality. We show theoretically that a positively biased sender will increase cheating when presented with information about the deception of his peers. The experimental data confirm this. We conclude that concern for relative standing does play a role in the decision to deceive.
I was PI for the ESRC standard grant "The Forecasting Efficiency Of Prediction Markets", 2021-2024. The CI was Christos A. Ioannou and the postdoctoral Research Fellow was Sergei Mikhalishchev. I was CI in the French AAPG2021 research grant "Bounded Rationality in Prediction Markets", 2022-2025.
Prediction markets leverage the wisdom of the crowd, by aggregating information that is dispersed among individuals. The mechanism is intuitive. Traders buy and sell securities, which pay £1 only if a specific event occurs (e.g. Trump wins the next US presidential election) and £0 otherwise. On the one hand, if the security price is low and some traders have private information that the event is highly likely, they will buy the security; consequently, its price will go up. On the other hand, if the security price is high and some traders have private information that the event is highly unlikely, they will sell the security, hence its price will go down. Such price movements could reveal to a trader information that others might have, prompting her to update her beliefs and either buy or sell the security, thus, further revealing to other traders some of her own private information. The final price, normalized to be between 0 and 1, is interpreted as the public's probability of the event occurring. Information gets aggregated if the final price (or probability) is close to the true outcome (0 or 1).
Our research aims to understand under which conditions the prediction markets (and financial markets more generally) are an effective tool in aggregating information. This is important because making predictions about future events is an inescapable part of decision making. Revenues for the forecasting industry are estimated at around $300 billion (Atanasov et al. (2017)), hence, even slightly better predictions are economically beneficial for individuals, governments, firms and organizations.
Prediction markets have been analysed both theoretically and experimentally. Our research aims to improve on both these dimensions and add a third, by conducting private prediction markets with firms and organisations. We have studied information aggregation under ambiguity averse preferences, showing theoretically and experimentally how separable securities fail to aggregate information because traders are stuck on the wrong price. We propose a new class, called strongly separable securities, which always aggregate information. However, an outside market maker may not be able to design such securities unless he knows the information structure of traders. We have analysed information aggregation in dynamic settings with unawareness, where information aggregation usually fails and is achieved only if traders are able to increase their awareness by observing counterfactual prices. We have studied settings where traders can acquire costly information signals, providing a full characterisation of which securities aggregate information, which surprisingly depends only on their payoff structure.
Finally, we have started a new line of research, by studying prediction markets in the field. In particular, we have built a prediction market platform, Calimantic.com, and we collaborate with firms and organisations in order to deploy private prediction markets with their employees. This has not been done before and it is interesting because it involves participants who are experienced in making predictions about real-world events, about their firm and their industry.
Learn MoreI co-organise the following seminars and conferences:
The main collaborators in the Competition and Markets Authority (CMA) Durham partnership are the CMA Microeconomics Unit, the Department of Economics and Durham Research in Economic Analysis and Mechanisms. You can find more about our joint actions and events by clicking below.
CMA Durham PartnershipWe have created a Prediction Markets platform and we run private prediction markets with firms and organisations. Contact me if you are interested to participate.
CalimanticI have organised panel discussions and short courses on the economics of blockchain and cryptocurrencies, such as Investing in Crypto Assets and Decentralised Finance, that took place on March 31 2021. You can find more information here. I advised Aaro Capital, a fund of funds specialised in crypto investments, between 2018-2024, writing several reports on the economics of blockchain. I cofounded Nelum, which issued the Living Paintings of artist Costas Tsoclis.
After teaching International Trade Theory for more than 10 years, I wrote a book, "Six Easy Models of International Trade Theory". It provides a short and concise introduction to the main theories of international trade, addressing the following questions. Are there gains for a country that engages in free trade? Which goods does it export and import? What happens to its income distribution? What are the implications for consumers and producers when it restricts trade, for example by imposing import tariffs?
Six Easy Models of International Trade TheoryI like to program recreationally. Part of my first sabbatical was (regrettably) devoted in learning to program iOS apps, such as Group Debts, about recording and sharing expenses among groups, and Ticket Holder, about storing and organizing ticket codes. Since 2011, they have been downloaded around 43000 times.
My newest app is a Chrome Extension which aims to protect the users' privacy and sanitize their social media timeline by browsing the web with multiple AI Personas.
Sybil AIHow to prove a theorem: